If you’re reading these words, you are almost certainly doing so because you choose to, of your own volition. What brings you here? Perhaps you are tired of tyranny and want to liberate yourself and others. Perhaps your eyes have been opened to all the wrong in the world—and to the fact that attacks on human freedom are the underlying pattern.
Whatever the case, no one is holding a gun to your head. You consent to be here.
When we rank-order our needs, perhaps the way Abraham Maslow did, the need that comes before all the others is the need NOT to have violence done to us. Yet we are all denied this choice on a daily basis. We are denied our right to consent, and governments are the worst offenders of all.
If you have awoken to this reality, then you know that there is a fundamental moral principle at work, and that certain people consistently violate it. There are variations on what to call the principle, but the idea goes something like this:
One ought never to threaten or initiate force against innocent people.
This is usually referred to as the nonaggression principle (NAP).
Morality Is Child’s Play
There are various ways in which this principle can be justified, both philosophically and practically. For now, we might simply appeal to your intuition, because you likely already recognize the principle as a natural aspect of life. Some part of you knows—and has known for as long as you can remember—that it is wrong to harm innocent people.
Since you were a child, you also knew, intuitively, that there is a difference between the status of a person who hits first and the person who defends himself. “Hey, he STARTED it!” is a natural reaction among even very young children. Hence, we distinguish between initiated, coercive force and any defensive or retaliatory force that may be used in response.
The NAP is a crucial and essential first principle to guide our actions. But is it enough? Can it account for all situations? Does it provide a complete defense of individual rights and freedoms?
Limits of the NAP
With deeper inquiry, two major questions arise:
What about things that don’t quite seem like force, but that we know are wrong?
What about things that are clearly coercive, but that aren’t wrong in certain circumstances?
Things that don’t quite seem like force, but are wrong nonetheless
Let us say you left your bike at the end of your driveway. You meant to go back for it, but then you fell asleep. In the night, someone walks three steps onto your property, grabs your bike, and pedals off, never to be seen again.
You don’t need a philosopher to tell you that theft is wrong—that this violated your rights. But was it force? The thief didn’t knock you down and take your bike. The thief didn’t even jump a fence or break a lock. He just stepped onto your driveway and stole your property. That isn’t force in the classic sense that most people understand, yet it is still wrong.
Most of us also see trespass as a violation of some kind, and the thief clearly trespassed to get that bike. Yet, in this case, the trespass wasn’t violent.
We generally share this same understanding of fraud—using deception to deprive someone of property. Fraud may be accomplished without the use of physical force, yet we still consider it wrong.
The same moral awareness applies to grievous coercion techniques such as brainwashing, extortion, and other forms of extreme manipulation, in which people are compelled to do things they would not otherwise do. This can be accomplished without direct physical force, but we still see it as a violation because it deprives the victim of personal agency.
One workaround for these conundrums is to broaden the definition of what qualifies as force. We could define one’s property and personal agency as extensions of one’s existence as an individual being—of one’s ownership of oneself. Force, then, could include violations of property and self-ownership.
In a philosophical sense, we would be right to do so. But this still leaves us with a problem. When most people think of force, they think of physical force. Thus, we will always have to explain our broadened definition.
Alternatively, we could define “aggression” in the nonaggression principle to include this sort of non-physical force. But is this the best way?
Things that are force, but are okay with consent
A further conundrum (and ultimately the source of a potential answer) comes from our second question. What about things that are forceful, but are allowed so long as the target of the force says it’s okay? In other words, what if the person consents?
For example,
With consent, it is competing in a martial arts tournament.
Without consent, it is assault.
With consent, it is leaving your bike for your friend to borrow.
Without consent, it is theft.
With consent, it is lovemaking.
Without consent, it is rape.
Consent is central to the question of rights. Indeed, this analysis shows us that the question Was it consensual? is even more fundamental than Was force initiated?
It doesn’t take a philosophy degree to understand this. We all have an intuitive sense that consent is paramount.
When you engage in a consensual transaction with someone else, you don’t think much about the consent aspect. It is simply understood as a part of the transaction: We are agreeing to this. When you are forced into a transaction with which you do not agree, the consent aspect is foremost in your mind: Hey, I didn’t agree to this!
In other words, consent is a fundamental aspect of life and a natural part of your moral knowledge—so much so that it is organically understood in the first transaction and a source of moral outrage in the second.
We still have to define precisely what consent is and when it applies. We will also want to explore further where consent comes from and why it is so important. But we have the makings of a principle here.
Somehow, some way, consent matters.
Stay tuned for Part 2, next week.
I’m not sure what exactly it is today, maybe it’s that all societies have a life span and we are living in the final stages of ours, but it seems today there is this propensity towards evil. This is nothing new. Time after time people are confronted with doing what is right or many times lining their own pockets. This may include hurting others to propel themselves forward. If you just do what you’re told, don’t upset the apple cart, you will become exorbitantly rich, or be principled and be destroyed.
Turning a blind eye to a crime makes you complicit and in some cases as guilty as those involved. In a way you are obstructing what is right, obstructing justice. Over 2000 years ago Pontius Polatus gave a crowd a choice to crucify Barabbas, a known murderer, or Jesus, the crowd overwhelmingly chose Jesus. Don’t we see the same thing over and over again today. People we thought were honorable and credible fall. People put in power to protect us choose money over the safety of their constituents. Maybe it’s me but in my sixty years of breathing I never remember a time where it was more important to advocate for your family and yourself. It’s seems in today’s America people won’t flinch as they crush you into dust. Take care of yourself.
Great start! Consent matters. But there can be no consent with coercion. There can be no consent with deception. Yet this is what they did with the Covid fraud. They deliberately killed innocent people to create fear to get you and your family injected.
The first crime was murder, mainly through deadly hospital protocol. The second larger crime was the coercion and deception to get billions injected.